Sunday, 24 February 2019

Does Martin Luther believe in Free Will?


The following is an excerpt from pages 49 to 51 of the book Bondage of the Will, edited by J.I. Packer, regarding Martin Luther's thoughts on the idea of "Free Will", as opposed to his worthy opponent Erasmus.

-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

This was just what Erasmus would not say. Standing in the semi-Pelagian Scholastic tradition, he champions the view that, though sin has weakened man, it has not made him utterly incapable of meritious action; in fact, says, Erasmus, the salvation of those who are saved is actually determined by a particular meritorious act which they perform in their own strength, without Divine assistance. There is, he affirms, a power in the human will (though, admittedly, a very little power only), 'by which man may apply himself to those things that lead to eternal salvation,' and thereby gain merit (though, admittedly, a very little merit only). It is by this meritorious application to spiritual concerns that salvation is secured. In expounding this opinion, Erasmus echoes the Scholastic theory of a distinction between congruent merit (meritum de congrou) and condign merit (meritum de condigno). The first of these, according to the theory, was that which a man attained by what he did in his own strength (ex puris naturalibus) in applying himself to spiritual concerns. It's effect was to make him a fit subject for the gift of internal grace. It did not positively oblige God to give internal grace (from this point of view, it was meritorious only which has hitherto stood in the way of God's giving it, i.e man's unworthiness of it and his unpreparedness for it; however, it was held to be a certain fact that God in mercy gives internal grace to all who have made themselves fit subjects for it. Grace (i.e. supernatural spiritual energy) having thus been given, it's recipient could use it to do works of a quality of goodness previously out of his reach, works which God was necessarily bound, as a matter of justice, to reward which further supplies of grace and ultimately, with heavenly glory. The merit which these works secured (condign merit) was meritorious in the strict sense, and put the Creator under a real obligation. The purpose of the whole theory was to hold together, on the one hand, the reality of God's freedom in giving salvation and, on the other, the reality of man's merit in earning it: to show that God really becomes man's debtor (because He is under obligation to reward man's merit) while yet at the same time remaining sovereign in salvation (because He gives grace which creates the merit freely and without obligation)

The distinction, of course, is purely verbal, and Luther sweeps it away. All ideas of merit, he insists, whatever names you give them and whatever distinctions you draw between them, come to the same thing - man performs some action independently of God which does in fact elicit a reward from God. On this basis salvation comes to man through God's response to what man has done. Man earns his passage; man, in the last analysis, save himself. And this is in principle Pelagianism. Erasmus had supposed that by stressing the smallness of the power which man can exercise, and of the merit offence of his Pelagian principles and moving closer to the Augustinian position, which denies all merit and ascribes salvation wholly to God. Not at all, says Luther; all that Erasmus and those whom he follows are really doing here is cheapening and debasing their own Pelagianism, by reducing the price of salvation. 'This hypocrisy of theirs results in their valuing and seeking to purchase the grace of God at a much cheaper rate than the Pelagians. The latter assert that it is not by a feeble something within us that we obtain grace. Now, if there must be error, those who say that the grace of God is priced high, and account it dear and costly, err less shamefully and presumptuously than those who teach that it's price is a tiny trifle, and account it cheap and contemptible' (pp. 293f).   To be an inferior kind of Pelagian in this way, however, is not, as Luther points out, to approach any nearer to the Augustinia position; it is merely to advertise to the world that, in addition to holding an unwarrantably high opinion of the natural powers of man, one also holds a shockingly low opinion of the oral demands of God's character. The semi-Pelagian compromise, says Warfield, amplifying Luther's thought at this point, 'while remaining Pelagian in principle, yet loses the high ethical position of works and fondly congratulating itself that it retains both, it merely falls between the stools and retains neither. It depends as truly as Pelagianism on works, but reduces those works on which it nevertheless depends to a vanishing point.' Pure Pelagianism is bad enough, for it tells us that we are able to earn our salvation, and this is to flatter man; but semi-Pelagianism is worse, for it tells us that we need hardly do anything to earn our salvation, and that is to belittle salvation and to insult God....

But there is a deeper reason why the doctrine of merit, in all its shapes and forms, must be rejected. The idea of a meritorious act is an idea of an independent act which is in no way necessitated by God for man or performed by God in man, but is carried out by man acting in some sense apart from God. And there is no such action as this in God's universe. The Creator directly energizes and controls all the acts of His creatures. All events are necessitated by His immutable, sovereign will. Human actions are genuinely spontaneous, and authentically express each man' s nature, for God works in all things according to their nature; but the fact that it is God who works all man's works in him means that human action can never be independent of God in the sense required for it to acquire merit in the manner the Pelagians envisage. Man cannot put God in his debt, because man does not stand apart from God as a free and independent agent. Luther thus undercuts the whole conception of merit by affirming the direct sovereignty of God over His world. What he is saying is that the Pelagian idea of merit is a Deistic idea, and has no place in a Theistic order of things such as the Bible depicts, in which God works al in all according to the counsel of His own will. Luther does not shrink from stating this truth in its bluntest form. God, he says, works every human deed, whether good or evil. He works in the evil man according to that man's nature, as He finds it. it is true that evel man is proximately and directly governed by Satan, the strong man who keeps his goods in peace; yet it is God the Creator who energizes Satan, according to his nature, and such power as Satan held and exercised by God's own appointment. When Satan acts, according to his nature, as God's enemy, he is being used, according to God's purpose, as God's own agent. Behind the revealed dualism of cosmic conflict between the devil and God lies the hidden mystery of absolute Divine sovereignty; evil is brought to expression only by the omnipotent working of the good God. 'Since God moves and works in all, He moves and works of necessity even in Satan and the ungodly. But he works according to what they themselves are, and what He finds them to be; which means, since they are evil and perverted themselves, that when they are impelled to action by this movement of Divine omnipotence they do only that which is perverted and evil. It is like a man riding a horse with only three, or two, good feet; his riding corresponds with what the horse is, which means that the horse goes badly . . . and so it bound to be, unless the horse is healed. Here you see that God works in and by evil men, evil deeds results; yet God . . . is good, and cannot do evil; but he uses evil instruments . . . The fault which accounts for evil being done when God moves to action lies in these instruments, which God does not allow to be idle . . . ' (p. 204). Mysterious though this is in detail, yet if God is absolutely sovereign and omnipotent, working all in all, then it must in some form be true; and therefore we must reject out of hand all forms of the Deistic notion of God as an onlooker, passively watching the acts of man, in whose performance He plays no direct part. But that means that 'free-will' in Erasmus sense of an inherent power in man to act apart from God, simply does not exist. Only God has "free-will', for He is the only independent agent that there is. Man does not act independently of God's necessitating purpose (though he likes to hink he does), and therefore "free-will  is an empty name, an inapplicable title, when predicated of him.

No comments:

Post a Comment